-->
Search the ArchivesNavigationContact InformationThe Citizen Newspapers For Advertising Information Email us your news! For technical difficulties |
The Moral Argument: What I Am NOT ArguingA recent exchange with a blogger here convinced me that some people react rather than reflect. Instead of making an attempt at an actual assessment of my argument (or simply ignoring it because it is admittedly long), this blogger chose to project views on me that I neither harbored nor launched. Oscar Wilde said, "If you cannot answer a man's arguments, don't panic. You can always insult him." Typically, "answering a man's arguments" calls for understanding them. Our blogger chose to skip the middle man and go straight for the insult part. (Projecting is, after all, much easier than the difficult task of taking on the subtleties of an actual person's actual argument.) My essay in that other blog is one instance of what is often called the Moral Argument. The basic idea is this: The idea of the objectivity of morality makes sense within the context of a theistic worldview in a way that it does not within a naturalistic worldview. As Dostoevsky put it in The Brothers Karamazov, "If God does not exist, everything is permitted." [Note to Reactionary Blogger: If you intend to react to that little summary without reading farther--as you did in the other thread--don't expect a reply.] Here are several things that this is NOT arguing. (1) It is NOT arguing that religious believers display greater moral virtue than do atheists. There are virtuous atheists and vicious believers, and vice versa. Atheists tend to love their spouses and children at roughly the same rate as believers, and may be found responding to human crises with compassion and kindness. NOTHING in the argument implies otherwise. Therefore, it is utterly irrelevant to raise issues of whether the Christian Church has persecuted, whether there are virtuous and noble atheists or creepy Christians. And, of course, one would have to be profoundly confused to reply by suggesting that the proponent of a moral argument is "holier-than-thou" or boasting moral superiority. (An argument entirely different from the moral argument maintains that physicalism--the predominant view of human nature among naturalists--cannot make sense of the notion of rational inference, which is employed whenever we reason. One might as well urge that the proponent of the "Argument from Rational Inference" is saying that physicalists are dumber than theists. Similarly, it is sometimes argued that physicalists cannot account for the obvious phenomenon of consciousness. Should we think that proponents of such arguments are saying that all physicalists are doppelgangers?) (2) It is NOT arguing that religious believers have a means of knowing the difference between right and wrong that is unavailable to atheists. One need not open a Bible in order to know, say, that child molestation is wrong, that we ought to be kind, and that our children are to be nurtured. Atheists and believers have access to the same sources of moral knowledge in conscience and in reasoning from conscience. (This is not to deny that a biblical perspective DOES take a position on some moral issues that are not readily available to the human conscience. I have in mind some issues in sexual morality, etc.) (3) It is NOT arguing that any and all societies that abandon religious belief will necessarily fall into moral ruin. There are people who have argued this, and I think the matter is settled, IF settled, empirically and historically. But that argument is not at all a part of what is going on in the moral argument. (4) It is NOT arguing that there is no reason to be moral unless there are rewards and punishments waiting for us all (heaven and hell). Frankly, anyone who will do the right thing only to enjoy a reward or avoid a punishment is not being moral but prudent and self-interested. What, then, is the point? It is that moral realism--the belief that the world includes objective moral facts or properties--requires a particular sort of metaphysical and epistemological underpinning in order to be coherent. The argument holds that Nietzsche was right: the demise of God signals the death of morality. Nietzsche was a moral nihilist because he was an atheist. We should not have assumed that whether moral realism is true is indifferent to which worldview is true. Why should anyone have thought a thing like that? The argument, then, is that theism has the resources for providing a metaphysical and epistemological account that is unavailable to the consistent naturalist. (And, happily, most naturalists are inconsistent with the implications of their worldview.) And so, insofar as we believe that some things are objectively right and others objectively wrong, we have some reason for preferring theism over naturalism. As the essay concludes, the choices seem to come down to agreeing with either the moral skeptic, David Hume or the moral realist, Thomas Reid. BOTH maintained that we find ourselves with a fund of moral beliefs that are not the product of rational inference but spring spontaneously from our "constitution." But whereas Hume had no reason to think that such "constitutional" beliefs would correspond to anything true, Reid, who was a theist, did. muddle's blog | login to post comments |